Home :: Books :: History  

Arts & Photography
Audio CDs
Audiocassettes
Biographies & Memoirs
Business & Investing
Children's Books
Christianity
Comics & Graphic Novels
Computers & Internet
Cooking, Food & Wine
Entertainment
Gay & Lesbian
Health, Mind & Body
History

Home & Garden
Horror
Literature & Fiction
Mystery & Thrillers
Nonfiction
Outdoors & Nature
Parenting & Families
Professional & Technical
Reference
Religion & Spirituality
Romance
Science
Science Fiction & Fantasy
Sports
Teens
Travel
Women's Fiction
German Idealism: The Struggle Against Subjectivism, 1781-1801

German Idealism: The Struggle Against Subjectivism, 1781-1801

List Price: $65.00
Your Price: $56.11
Product Info Reviews

<< 1 >>

Rating: 5 stars
Summary: tous philosophous sozein (saving the philosophers)
Review: Among the silliest of the many silly ways of criticizing something is to complain that it is not what it has no pretense of being. The title of Beiser's book, as well as its length and its rather hefty price, make it sufficiently clear that it is not intended as a general popular introduction to all German Idealism. Rather, it is scholarly inquiry into a phase of German Idealism that, while not altogether neglected, is too often regarded as merely a preparation for Hegel's triumphant system. That Beiser's study cuts off at 1801 relieves him of the need to deal with Hegel apart from his relation to Fichte and Schelling, and it no doubt reveals the bias of the reviewer from Cambridge that, seemingly having missed this point, he does not also accuse Beiser of neglecting to speak about Schelling's essay on the Human Freedom, his philosophy of Mythology and Revelation, Fichte's later systems, or perhaps even Solger's aesthetics, all of which also fall within the fold of German Idealism.
Granting the self-imposed temporal constraints of his inquiry, Beiser's aim is not to exclude or marginalize Hegel and deny his significance for German idealism, but rather to rescue the singular originality and grandeur of moments within the history of German Idealism that have fallen into the shadow of the leviathan to which they gave birth. While this very effort is somewhat compromised by Beiser's epistemological orientation, and I do not entirely agree with his ultimate reading of German Idealism as a neo-Platonism anticipating the Neo-Kantianism of Hermann Cohen and Ernst Cassirer, I nevertheless admire the rigor and clarity of this work, and would strongly recommend to all those who have a more than dilettantish interest in German philosophy.

Rating: 5 stars
Summary: Beiser is a careful reader -
Review: Beiser notes, almost nonchalantly, that "this study of German idealism omits Hegel, and it is indeed a reaction against the Hegelian legacy" because he regards Hegel as "tendentious" and "unoriginal" (claims, of course, that can be made for any well-known historical figure). Setting aside the question whether ignoring Hegel in such a work is useful or even valid (I personally don't), attempting a general introductory text on German idealism using this approach is simply absurd. I could never recommend this book for someone wishing to gain a better understanding of German idealism, since it would be so misleading as to be false. If it wasn't the author's intent to write such an introduction, then he should have structured his work differently (including using a different title, such as "German Idealism Before Hegel"). If the reader clearly understood that this work was far from being a general overview, then it could be read with beneficial results. The way it stands, however, it would be like claiming to write an introduction to Greek philosophy, but to not include Plato and Aristotle, since their only value was to bring together and recapitulate the major ideas of the Pre-Socratics.

Rating: 5 stars
Summary: Beiser is a careful reader -
Review: The review below which claims that Beiser says that Hegel is "tendentious" is not correct. Beiser's text reads, "Hegel's history of the period, which interprets it as a progression culminating in his own system, is tendentious philosophically, and anachronistic historically" (ix). This is certainly not the same as claiming that Hegel is tendentious. In addition, Beiser's criticism is quite correct; Hegel's history of philosophy is quite tendentious.

Another reviewer claims that Beiser omits Kant from this text. This is an absurd claim. The first section of the book, which spans 200 pages, is about Kant.

Rating: 2 stars
Summary: Better works available
Review: There are better works available on German Idealism than this 600 page volume, which is unfortunate because it would indeed have been handy to have an accurate portrayal of the philosophical period it purports to describe, and to have it in English. Despite Beiser's claim to refrain from treating the relationships between this epoch's key figures -- namely Fichte, Schelling, Holderlin, and Hegel (the ommission of the latter makes the book's title simply inaccurate) -- he does indeed construct a narrative from the records of their engagements with each other (letters, etc). All these men knew each other, and they all read each other's work, and Idealism would not have existed in the form it took were this not the case. While other reviewers lament a treatment of Hegel, I would stress the absence of Kant in this book: Beiser may well argue against a Hegel bias in academic research (although this is surely wrong), but were it not for Kant German Idealism would never have existed in the first place (and this is the second reason why the title is misleading). For those who want to understand Idealism, it means that works by other authors should be read (or at the very least consulted, if only to appraise Beiser's claims to be authoritative, something which is evidenced throughout by his strident tone), and, as with all real scholarship, articles as well. Superb alternative works that treat Kant, Fichte, Schelling, Holderlin, and Hegel have been written by Dieter Henrich, Eckhart Forster, and Paul Guyer, and all exist in English; Manfred Frank's distinguished work is in German; and the French have contributed with incisive works on Hegel (by Jean Hyppolite) and on the important relation of the Early German Romantic's critical theory to the philosophy of Idealism (by Jean-Luc Nancy and Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe), and all are available in English translation; lastly, a masterful exposition of Schelling's thought by Jean-Francois Courtine is available in French. In sum, a book on "German Idealism" that lops off Kant on the one end and Hegel on the other just cannot be said to have covered the ground that the title implies.


<< 1 >>

© 2004, ReviewFocus or its affiliates