Home :: Books :: Entertainment  

Arts & Photography
Audio CDs
Audiocassettes
Biographies & Memoirs
Business & Investing
Children's Books
Christianity
Comics & Graphic Novels
Computers & Internet
Cooking, Food & Wine
Entertainment

Gay & Lesbian
Health, Mind & Body
History
Home & Garden
Horror
Literature & Fiction
Mystery & Thrillers
Nonfiction
Outdoors & Nature
Parenting & Families
Professional & Technical
Reference
Religion & Spirituality
Romance
Science
Science Fiction & Fantasy
Sports
Teens
Travel
Women's Fiction
The Sociology of Philosophies: A Global Theory of Intellectual Change

The Sociology of Philosophies: A Global Theory of Intellectual Change

List Price: $27.50
Your Price: $27.50
Product Info Reviews

<< 1 >>

Rating: 5 stars
Summary: Change as a constant...
Review: 'I am thinking' is irrefutable because 'I am not thinking' nevertheless displays oneself thinking.
-- p. 858

The book 'The Sociology of Philosophies' purports to be 'The first comprehensive history of world philosophy,' as well as 'a social history of global intellectual life.' Collins in this book takes as his subject the whole of human intellectual endeavour, exploring the strands and developments of philosophical thought in all the major cultures of the world.

Collins begins this weighty and, at times, hyper-intellectual tome by building a theory of intellectualism, ritual, education, and philosophical reflection. He identifies two of the longest and most dominant philosophical strands as being those arising in Greece and China.

Collins posits the theory that intellectual pursuits do not arise in a vacuum, and are more of a societal and communal development than an individual pursuit or achievement.

'That ideas are not rooted in individuals is hard to accept because it seems to offend against a key epistemological point. Here the question is analytically distinct from the propensity to worship intellectual heroes.'

However, when one looks at the history of ideas, they usually arise in groups. While there are certainly key individuals who arose at different times in history, it is also true that there are patterns -- the age of philosophy in Greece, the Renaissance in Italy, etc. There is a particular atmosphere and sociological aspect to the culture that encourages and develops intellectual development that is unique to each, and leads to differing developments.

After exploring this history and the rituals of intellectuals and intellectualism (which is little acknowledged among scholars in the West), Collins explores who the major individuals are, who the minor individuals are, and what places they occupy in the chain of intellectual history. These chains are most pronounced in developments from Greece and developments from China; the Chinese strands continue through almost all subsequent Eastern thought, which is always responding to or reacting against key ideas formed there; in Western thought, almost all philosophical and intellectual development does the same with regard to the Greek development.

Collins proceeds from this to a theoretical framework (in which he develops more closely the Greek philosophical reflective framework, being the one from which Collins was educated, and thus the dominant underpinning of his writing) that explores the importance and rarity of true creativity. From this, he continues, doing a comparative analysis of intellectual communities, drawing in, in addition to Ancient Greece and Ancient China, India, Japan, Neo-Confucian China, Medieval Christendom, Islamic philosophies, Jewish philosophical development, then surveying modern western philosophies, French, German, and British.

Strong historical themes, political and other intellectual developments (such as the shift from faith-based to experimental-based knowledge and the rise of scientific method and mathematical objectivism) are included in his analysis. Collins concludes this work with Meta-Reflections, in which he explores the sequence and branches in the production of ideas socially (exploring the future of philosophy, which Collins states is 'a partisan theme which announces that the era of foundational questions is over. The call for the end of philosophy is recurrent, a standard ploy in intergenerational rearrangements, usually a prelude to a new round of deep troubles and new creativity.'

Collins' meta-reflections also include an epilogue on sociological realism. The quote that starts this review comes from this section. Self-evident truths are explored here.

'Virtually no one actually doubts the reality of the world of ordinary experience. It is only within specialised intellectual networks that the question has arisen whether this banal reality can be proven to a high standard of argument; and even intellectuals, when they are 'off duty', go back to assuming the reality of the ordinary time-space world.'

Sociological realism accepts the world as it is, which is not always the case with philosophy, even though philosophy purports to explain the world. This is a disconnect that occurs frequently in history. Collins further looks to mathematics and 'rapid-discovery science' for complications and developmental pieces in the intellectual history of the world.

Collins includes an extensive bibliography (worth the value of the book in itself), indexes of persons and of ideas, keys and timelines to figures, and a very interesting appendix entitled 'The Clustering of Contemporaneous Creativity', in which the ebb and flow of intellectual development on a global scale is examined and shows interesting results. He charts here the 'cultural production' of intellectuals, and their influence on their respective cultures. He traces such developments across hundreds of major and minor figures, determining fewer than 20 'isolates' in any cultural strand, and those being only among the minor figures.

Rating: 5 stars
Summary: Reading Global History of Philosophy With a Thesis
Review: For all interested in global history of philosophy, this is the book to get.

First, each section on a particular philosophical tradition (e.g. ancient Greece, Indian, Medieval Islamic, Chinese, Modern) is an interesting high-level history of tradition in its own rights. This alone makes the price tag worthwhile.

More importantly, Collins included very interesting insights about individual period that is not covered by other general histories:
1) How some schools of thoughts become popular not because they are correct but because they are extreme
2) Parallelisms that occur in different periods of the same tradition (e.g. Post-Shankara positions in India has its parallel during the hey-day of Buddhist philosophy)
3) Parallelisms that occur across traditions (e.g. compelling coverage of how medieval Christian & Islamic philospophy shares a similar structure)

With these characteristics, I think this book clearly satisfies the need us interested in global history of philosophy, for which Collins is clearly very passionate about.

On the sociology theoretical piece, I think the theory is fine: it articulates a lot of aspects of which most students of philosophy has a vague sense. The theory is almost 'common sense'-- just that it doesn't seem to have been clearly articulated that way in academic circles. As such, the theory piece is less interesting, but it is not intruding and it provides a sound umbrella thesis for Collins' insights on individual traditions.

Lastly, one point about the 'data' that Collins use-- the 'maps' that link the different philosophers in networks. I think it is interesting to read (because it includes a lot of interesting names-- familiar or otherwise), but they don't really provide the 'data' on which the sociological theory can be based. I think Collins himself recognized this-- and thus his appendix about the important 'isolates' like Ibn Sina.

Rating: 5 stars
Summary: A new way to view philosophy
Review: I have a Ph.D. in history of philosophy, but I now follow it as an interested layman rather than a professional. In short, this review is written from the viewpoint of someone whose background and interests lie in philosophy rather than sociology.

For me, this was an interesting and useful book for a couple of reasons:

1. It discusses philosophers in the context of social networks, where the thinkers are linked by relationships such as: was the student of, reacted against, was married to the sister of, etc.

Often, philosophy is taught (or studied) by looking only at the works of philosophers, in isolation from the philosophers' relationships with others around them. Placing a philosopher in the context of a network of relationships helps considerably in understanding what the philosopher is trying to do, and why. In short, it can help you better to understand any particular philosopher that you are studying.

2. I found the author's notion of an "attention space" very interesting. The notion of an "attention space" in the history of philosophy seems to me similar to Thomas Kuhn's notion of a "paradigm" in the history of science. Philosophers' roles in the history of philosophy are described as moving the attention space, or elaborating within the attention space, and so on, where moving the attention space is comparable to Kuhn's "paradigm shift" and elaborating within the attention space is comparable to Kuhn's "normal science". This approach to the history of philosophy is, I think helpful. It gives you genuine insight into the history of philosophy.

I recommend this book. You may not wish to read it all -- I didn't -- but if you dip into it here and there, at spots that look interesting to you, you will encounter ideas and concepts that are useful, stimulating and thought-provoking.

Rating: 5 stars
Summary: I seriously doubt...
Review: I mean seriously, how many of you have taken the time to comprehend the true value of this book?

... Take your time. The book isn't going anywhere. Well, ... not without you it isn't.

Am I right?

Rating: 5 stars
Summary: Great classroom reference
Review: I received this welcome book free in the mail years ago with the suggestion that it be a text book for a philosophy course. While it certainly is an important, interesting book on philosophy, it offers little as a philosophy text book. But over the years I have found lots of opportunities to refer to it in class as a resource.
Some specific things I find come up frequently:
1. The concept of the sociological cogito -- this strikes me as a wonderful way of applying Augustine, via Descartes' cogito via Leibniz, Hegel, Wittgenstein (private language argument) to interest the class on what we know for certain. It was the first I saw the argument presented this lucidly.
2. Applying the template of social networks to the development of ideas - and this I connect to current complex systems work such as Kennedy's Swarm Intelligence. I love passing the book around so everyone can see the network charts.
3. The relationship between points of view moving through intellectual space following standard patterns, much as Hegelian dialectic describes, but in easier terms.
4. Since I also routinely discuss sociologizing sociology, it certainly is fair that I discuss sociologizing philosophy as well.

There is a disappointment: the book stops. Understood, the effort would have been a tremendous one as the information explosion changes the patterns. But this is precisely the concern. What changes with the information explosion? We did not have to touch Quine to be strongly influenced though meeting him was certainly an event to be remembered. This is an approach I would like to see explored further.


Rating: 5 stars
Summary: Sociology of Philosophy Has Come of Age!
Review: I was disappointed, but not entirely surprised, by A.C. Grayling's superficial grasp of Randall Collins's achievement in The Sociology of Philosophies (New York Times Sunday Book Review, 27 September). I write as someone who holds a doctorate in the history and philosophy of science but who now holds a professorial chair in sociology and works in the terrain staked out in Collins's book, which is often called "social epistemology." Grayling argues that Collins fails to appreciate the perennial character of philosophical argument because of his exclusive focus on the social networks that develop and transmit ideas. This is not quite right. Rather, Collins wants to explain this perenniality in terms of social networks. Given the vast numbers of philosophers, and the variety of arguments they have had over the last 2500 years, how is it that they seem reducible to a handful of general questions and representative figures? Grayling seems to believe that everybody has been asking the same questions but only very few have done a really good job answering them. Yet, it is little more than a finger exercise in the history and sociology of thought to show that posing questions in similar terms does not necessarily mean that the same question is being asked. And even figures as perennial as Plato and Aristotle have stood for different things at different times. The appearance of "depth" in philosophical matters that Grayling wishes to convey is, in sociological terms, shorthand for the collected means by which philosophers maintain their institutional presence. It is quite literally a myth, one comparable to the belief that priests are holier, or scientists smarter, than the run of humanity. However, it would be mistake -- again one that Grayling makes -- to conclude that Collins is merely concerned more with the social context surrounding the philosophical ideas than the ideas themselves. On the contrary, for Collins, sociology is essential for understanding the nature of philosophical ideas and argument, especially what counts as a good answer to a question. This explains why the perception of philosophical depth and superficiality has varied so much in history. For example, Grayling claims that we are now making "slow progress" on the problem of mind. Yet, only a generation ago -- under the influence of Ryle and Wittgenstein -- it was fashionable to hold that this was a pseudo-problem. What changed in the interim were the criteria of a good answer. Philosophers have become much more accountable to the findings of experimental science, on the one hand, and the experiences of diversely situated cultures, on the other. A solution to the problem of mind that satisfies both constituencies will be, indeed, difficult. But from a sociological standpoint, "depth" is a euphemism for philosophy's insecure institutional position, which requires that it reconciles the interests of these largely opposed groups. I was not surprised by Grayling's response because sociology has traditionally met its strongest opposition when studying forms of knowledge: religion, science, and now philosophy. There are successful precedents of theologians using the sociology of religion to understand and critique their own practices. If the Science Wars simmer down, the sociology of science may play a similar role. Hopefully, philosophy will not be the last holdout -- though, as Hegel said, the Owl of Minerva takes flight at dusk...

Rating: 5 stars
Summary: What is like the life of scholar
Review: The first review below focused on the theoretical position of this book. I'll put some complementary remarks on that review.
1. Collins's theoretical approach is known as network theory in the field of sociological theories. it was derived from the exchange theory. its premise come from rational choice theorem of neoclassical economics. overall analyses of exchange theory and network are similar. But Collins's analysis in this book is a bit different. in network theory, the network is considered as resource or exogenous factor to the function of individual action. But Collins treats it as causal or determinant factor not simply environmental reference point. Theoretical position of scholar is determined by incumbent fractions of the field. Not only one¡¯s preference but currently unoccupied terrain determines one¡¯s position in the attention space of scientific community.
2. Collins demystifying the romantic perception of knowledge production: knowledge or art is not the offshoot of genius but that of community. In this regard, Collins take the point of sociology of science not sociology of knowledge. The former perceives the knowledge as determined or affected by external factor of network, while the latter does by class or socioeconomic interest. They seems not that different. But quite different actually. The latter take the content of knowledge or artwork as dependent variable against the independent variable ie, the broad framework of class interest. It¡¯s the basic position of traditional Marxist. But Sociology of science narrows the scope of independent variable down to community of scholars. And the works of scholar is seen as commodity in the marketplace. Here the reward is not money but the fame.

Rating: 5 stars
Summary: Tons of cow
Review: This book, THE SOCIOLOGY OF PHILOSOPHIES by Randall Collins, is large. If I had a lot more time, I might search the text and all of its charts for the name of David Friedrich Strauss, author of the German study, THE LIFE OF JESUS CRITICALLY EXAMINED translated into English by George Eliot in 1845. There is no listing in the index of this book for Strauss, but the name D. F. Strauss appears in the text in a paragraph on page 621 which also mentions Darwin, and on some charts, such as Figure 13.1 GERMAN NETWORK, 1835-1900: NEO-KANTIANS, HISTORICISTS, POSITIVISTS, PSYCHOLOGISTS on page 690, where it even appears in a rectangle like the names Hegel, Schelling, Hegel again, and Schleiermacher near the top of the chart. The rectangles might indicate a level of fame that assumed that certain of their books had been read, though George Eliot once wrote, "but I do not know one person who is likely to read the book through, do you?" Similarly, by size, this book might be considered the most professionally encompassing but intellectually democratic attempt to offer a theory (the law of small numbers) that approaches philosophical thought in the manner which socialized religion has used to convert religious belief to something which it can find useful.

While some outstanding experts on humor, like Freud and Heine, are mentioned in this book, the index does not provide lists for jokes. I tried looking up the key terms in the line, "Science is a sacred cow." The number of entries on Schools, Science, and Secularization only list a few pages, from 609 to 613, on anti-scientific intellectuals. There are no entries for Cow, but it would be between the listings for Courts and courtiers and for Creativity, which includes a bit (see pages 44-46, 52) on a discussion of emotional energy. Comedy would be found between the listings for "Cogito ergo sum" and Conflict as source of intellectual change. Instead of offering comedy as a subject, the index suggests, "See also Opposition, division of attention space by." (p. 1091). That's close enough for me.

Rating: 5 stars
Summary: Tons of cow
Review: This book, THE SOCIOLOGY OF PHILOSOPHIES by Randall Collins, is large. If I had a lot more time, I might search the text and all of its charts for the name of David Friedrich Strauss, author of the German study, THE LIFE OF JESUS CRITICALLY EXAMINED translated into English by George Eliot in 1845. There is no listing in the index of this book for Strauss, but the name D. F. Strauss appears in the text in a paragraph on page 621 which also mentions Darwin, and on some charts, such as Figure 13.1 GERMAN NETWORK, 1835-1900: NEO-KANTIANS, HISTORICISTS, POSITIVISTS, PSYCHOLOGISTS on page 690, where it even appears in a rectangle like the names Hegel, Schelling, Hegel again, and Schleiermacher near the top of the chart. The rectangles might indicate a level of fame that assumed that certain of their books had been read, though George Eliot once wrote, "but I do not know one person who is likely to read the book through, do you?" Similarly, by size, this book might be considered the most professionally encompassing but intellectually democratic attempt to offer a theory (the law of small numbers) that approaches philosophical thought in the manner which socialized religion has used to convert religious belief to something which it can find useful.

While some outstanding experts on humor, like Freud and Heine, are mentioned in this book, the index does not provide lists for jokes. I tried looking up the key terms in the line, "Science is a sacred cow." The number of entries on Schools, Science, and Secularization only list a few pages, from 609 to 613, on anti-scientific intellectuals. There are no entries for Cow, but it would be between the listings for Courts and courtiers and for Creativity, which includes a bit (see pages 44-46, 52) on a discussion of emotional energy. Comedy would be found between the listings for "Cogito ergo sum" and Conflict as source of intellectual change. Instead of offering comedy as a subject, the index suggests, "See also Opposition, division of attention space by." (p. 1091). That's close enough for me.

Rating: 5 stars
Summary: An amazing achievement, a fascinating read
Review: This is a remarkable book. The breadth of knowledge it displays is impressive enough, but this is not simply an encyclopedic tour through the world (literally, the world) of philosophy. It's a sustained piece of sociological analysis, clearly and accessibly written, well organized and trenchantly argued --- in short, an intellectual treat in almost every way.


<< 1 >>

© 2004, ReviewFocus or its affiliates